Backround
Definition
Presentation over a site
Models
This entry is about the article
Some Thoughts on the Future of Category Theory
In: A. Carboni, M. Pedicchio, G. Rosolini (ed.s)
Category Theory,
Proceedings of the International Conference held in Como,
Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1488, Springer (1991)
about the formalization of the “objective logic” of Hegelian metaphysics (Science of Logic) and in particular (implicitly) the notion of cohesive toposes. (See there for further references and other background material).
A closely related text is Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's "lauter Einsen".
The article is written in a style typical for Lawvere, where precise general abstract category theoretic and topos theoretic situations are discussed more in prose than in the usual style of mathematical writing. The thoughts revolve around a topic that Lawvere takes up in various later articles, which are all listed in the References-section at cohesive topos. In the following we try to illuminate what the article here is saying. Of course such an exegesis may or may not accurately reflect some of the original author’s actual intentions.
Pages 6 to 8 in section II of the text is to a large extent a proposal that there is a useful formalization of the unity of opposites and their “Aufhebung” that governs Georg Hegel‘s metaphysics as laid out in his Science of Logic. The proposal is that a “determination of being and becoming” is expressed by an adjoint modality. The tautological example is “pure being” and refinements thereof such as (flat modality sharp modality) characterize more determinate ways of entities to be.
Specifically, the notion of a category of being that Lawvere discusses (following terminology in Hegel's Science of Logic) in Some Thoughts on the Future of Category Theory is the notion that more recently he has been calling a category of cohesion . The following tries to illuminate a bit what’s going on .
We restrict attention to the case that the category “of Being” is a topos and say cohesive topos for short. This is a topos that satisfies a small collection of simple but powerful axioms that are supposed to ensure that its objects may consistently be thought of as geometric spaces built out of points that are equipped with “cohesive” structure (for instance topological structure, or smooth structure, etc.). So the idea is to axiomatize big toposes in which geometry may take place.
We walk through the main bits of the article:
One axiom on a cohesive topos is that the global section geometric morphism to the given base topos has a further left adjoint to its inverse image , which we shall write , for reasons discussed below. This extra left adjoint has the interpretation that it sends any object to the set “of connected components”. What Lawvere calls a connected object in the article (p. 4) is hence one that is sent by to the terminal object.
Another axiom is that preserves finite products. This implies by the above that the collection of connected objects is closed under finite products. This appears on page 6. What he mentions there with reference to Hurewicz is that given a topos with such , it becomes canonically enriched over the base topos in a second way, a geometric way.
The meaning of this, like that of various other aspects of cohesive toposes, may be clearer as we make the evident step to cohesive (∞,1)-toposes. (But notice that this, while inspired by Lawvere, is not due to him.)
In this more encompassing context the extra left adjoint becomes a left adjoint (∞,1)-functor which we just write : it sends, one can show, any object to its geometric fundamental ∞-groupoid, for a notion of geometric paths intrinsic to the -topos. The fact that this preserves finite products then says that there is a notion of concordance of principal ∞-bundles in the -topos.
The next axiom on a cohesive topos says that there is also a further right adjoint to a total adjoint quadruple
such that both as well as are full and faithful.
This is what Lawvere is talking about from the bottom of p. 6 on. The downward functor that he mentions is . This has the interpretation of sending a cohesive space to its underlying set of points, as seen by the base topos . The left and right adjoint inclusions to this are and . These have the interpretation of sending a set of points to the corresponding space equipped with either discrete cohesion or codiscrete (indiscrete) cohesion . For instance in the case that cohesive structure is topological structure, this will be the discrete topology and the indiscrete topology, respectively, on a given set. Being full and faithful, and hence make a full subcategory of in two ways (p. 7), though only the image of will also be a subtopos, as he mentions on page 7.
(This has, by the way, an important implication that Lawvere does not seem to mention: it implies that we are entitled to the corresponding quasi-topos induced by the sub-topos. That, one can show, may be identified with the collection of concrete cohesive spaces. In the case of the cohesive topos for differential geometry, the concrete objects in this sense are precisely the diffeological spaces . )
He calls the subtopos given by the image of that of “pure Becoming” further down on p. 7, whereas the subcategory of discrete objects he calls that of “non Becoming”. One way one might understand this terminology is as follows:
whereas any old (∞,1)-topos is a collection of spaces , a cohesive (∞,1)-topos comes with the extra adjoint which, as mentioned above, has the interpretation of sending any space to its fundamental ∞-groupoid. Therefore there is an intrinsic notion of geometric paths in any cohesive -topos. This allows notably to define parallel transport along paths and higher parallel transport along higher dimensional paths, hence a kind of dynamics . In fact there is differential cohomology in every cohesive -topos.
Now, in a discrete object there are no non-trivial paths (formally because by the fact that is full and faithful and left adjoint to we have ), so there is “no dynamics” in a discrete object hence “no becoming”, if one wishes. Conversely in a codiscrete object every sequence of points whatsoever counts as a path, hence the distinction between the space and its “dynamics” disappears and so we have “pure becoming”, if one wishes.
Notice next that every adjoint triple induces an adjoint monad. In the present situation we get
This is what Lawvere calls the skeleton and the coskeleton on p. 7. In the (∞,1)-topos context the left adjoint has the interpretation of sending any object to the coefficient for cohomology of local systems with coefficients in .
The paragraph wrapping from page 7 to 8 comments on the possibility that the base topos is not just that of sets. Set, but something richer. An example of this is that of super cohesion (in the sense of superalgebra and supergeometry): the topos of smooth super-geometry is cohesive over the base topos of bare super-sets.
What follows on page 9 are thoughts which it seems Lawvere has not formalized further later on. But then on the bottom of p. 9 he gets to the axiomatic identification of infinitesimal or formal spaces in the cohesive topos. In the more recent article Axiomatic Cohesion what he says here on p. 9 is formalized as follows: he says an object is infinitesimal if the canonical morphism is an isomorphism. To see what this means, suppose that , hence that is connected. Then the isomorphism condition means that has exactly one global point. But may be bigger: it may be a formal neighbourhood of that point, for instance it may be infinitesimally thickened point that is formally dual to the ring of dual numbers. A general for which is an iso is hence a disjoint union of formal neighbourhoods of points.
Again, the meaning of this becomes more pronounced in the context of cohesive (∞,1)-toposes: there objects for which have the interpretation of being formal ∞-groupoids , for instance formally exponentiated L-∞ algebras. And so there is ∞-Lie theory canonically in every cohesive -topos.
More discussion of all this is at differential cohomology in a cohesive topos.
18 years later at the same place, Lawvere gives a lecture series on this topic: Cohesive Toposes – Combinatorial and Infinitesimal Cases.
Last revised on May 20, 2019 at 14:20:54. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.